http://www.e-ir.info/2013/11/14/review-eichmann-in-jerusalem/
Original essay:
Israel
hung Adolf Eichmann on May 31, 1962 after convicting him for his role as a Nazi
official during the Holocaust.[1]
He was a mid-level Nazi officer, responsible for organizing Jewish emigration
out of German held territory and for Jewish deportation to concentration and
extermination camps. Israel captured Eichmann, who was hiding in Argentina, in
1960 and deported him to Jerusalem where they tried and hung him. Hannah
Arendt, covered his trial for The New
Yorker compiling her essays into the book Eichmann in Jerusalem A Report on the Banality of Evil.[2]
Her book is not only a representation of Eichmann the man; it is a
representation of the “show trial David Ben-Gurion, Prime Minister of Israel,
had in mind when he decided to have Eichmann kidnaped in Argentina...”[3]
Her sarcastic criticism of the trial
contrasts problems with the preservation of the institution of law with the
necessary adjudication of Eichmann’s death, a moral imperative for the newly
formed Jewish state. Arendt argues
that the “irregularities and abnormalities of the trial [overshadowed] the
central moral, political, and even legal problems that the trial inevitably
posed.”[4]
Yet, she recognizes that the facts of the case warrant Eichmann’s death not
only for legal restitution but for Israel’s credibility as “’the State of the
Jews.’”[5]
Arendt
bases her reporting on trial transcripts and other primary and secondary source
documents.[6]
The book is more than a story; it is a carefully arranged legal brief. She
begins by describing the trial setting to include the actual courtroom paying
particular attention to editorialize the Israeli presuppositions, most notably
those of the Prime Minister, David Ben-Gurion.[7]
Arendt describes the court experience as being theatrical, a show whose maestro
is Ben-Gurion himself.[8]
In other words, he knows how the show will end and must direct its cast to that
ending. Arendt even concludes the opening chapter with Ben-Gurion saying he did
not “’care what verdict is delivered against Eichmann,’ [and that] it was
undeniably the sole task of the Jerusalem court to deliver one.”[9]
Her sarcastic opening portrays the “House of Justice” (the title of the first
chapter) as delivering predetermined justice which she will continue to argue
is a less than legally fair outcome, for
Eichmann.[10]
Those
presuppositions condemn Eichmann pre-trial. Arendt’s point in describing the
setting as such, illustrates one of the main themes of the book – that Eichmann
neither did nor could have received a fair trial, one which affords him
thorough due process. Her stage setter highlights that Eichmann’s ensuing trial
would challenge the institution of law with regard to jurisdiction (Jerusalem
v. Germany or an international court), legal due process, and evidentiary i.e.
criminal basis, nullum crimen, nulla
poena sine lege, relative to the nature of Eichmann’s crime ex ante vis-à-vis ex post facto.[11]
Once she sets the stage, Arendt provides, at length, background information of
Eichmann himself, of Eichmann’s role within the Nazi party, and of the
chronological evolution of the Holocaust.
The
most notable characteristic she portrays of Eichmann was that he, for the most
part, was unaware of the criminality of his actions. In fact, according to
Eichmann, he believed he was “’Not guilty, in the sense of the indictment.’”[12]
That sense called to question the ex post
facto principle on which Israel tried Eichmann. Eichmann believed Hitler’s
orders were law. What Eichmann did, consequently, constituted adherence to Nazi
Germany law, as he understood it.[13]
Israel, however, vis-à-vis the
prosecution, believed Eichmann’s adherence to Nazi law constituted, ex post facto, a crime first against the
Jewish people, and second against humanity, since the trial allegedly sought to
“’make no ethnic distinctions.’”[14]
The question she raised was to what extent was Eichmann a criminal? Arendt’s
handling of Eichmann leads the reader to understand that his role causes him to
act less like a human and more like some kind of machine.[15]
One of Arendt’s problems with the trial, then, was that the prosecution failed
to demonstrate the criminality of Eichmann as a “monster.”[16]
Moreover,
Arendt characterized Eichmann as thoughtless, to some extent a simpleminded man
both incapable of making his own decisions and not really wanting to.[17]
This simplemindedness made Eichmann almost a perfect candidate for his position
within the S.S. because he cared more about completing his tasks, obediently,
than he did with the effect of those tasks.[18]
Arendt demonstrated his thoughtlessness throughout the book, describing that he
remembered very little of what he did, with respect to the actions that led to
actual Jewish deaths. For example, she notes that “His memory proved to be
quite unreliable about what had actually happened…Eichmann remembered the
turning points in his own career…[but not] the turning points in the story of
Jewish extermination…”[19]
His failure to remember so many things did little to substantiate his behavior
as criminal, and it made the prosecution’s job harder painting a picture of the
scope of Eichmann’s involvement with Jewish deaths.
Arendt
explains that the trial expanded the canvas from Eichmann and his specific
crimes to include the sentiment of the Jewish people and the gravity of the
Holocaust in toto. This painting of a
much larger picture than just Eichmann further devalued, in Arendt’s opinion,
the validity of the trial altogether.[20]
The prosecution brought numerous witnesses to the stand to tell their
inconceivable stories of horror. Yet, many of those stories, in Arendt’s
re-explanation, did not connect directly to Eichmann. She points out that the
prosecution’s use of numerous, “immaterial” storytelling witnesses did little
to establish Eichmann’s guilt.[21]
In fact, they instead pointed to Jewish cooperation in the execution process.[22]
This was a huge problem for Arendt regarding the trial and regarding the
context of the trial because revealing Jewish involvement in effect reversed
the association of guilt from Eichmann directly to the Jewish people
indirectly. Yet, she does also find that this revelation exposed a more
dramatic conclusion “because it [offered] the most striking insight into the
totality of the moral collapse the Nazis caused in respectable European Society
– not only in Germany but in almost all countries, not only among the
persecutors but also among the victims.”[23]
Although the criminality basis, nullum
crimen, nulla poena sine lege, might have been loosely true in a technical
sense, the trial did not firmly establish a legal precedence for conviction. Arendt
instead established a moral basis on which criminality rightfully was
prosecuted.
Chronologically,
she guides the reader through the evolution of the Holocaust from the expulsion
of Jews from German territories, to their concentration in camps, ultimately to
their mass execution. Jewish deportation not only occurred in Germany, it occurred
in surrounding countries too. She devotes particular attention to deportations
from Western Europe – France, Belgium, Holland, Denmark, and Italy – the
Balkans – Yugoslavia, Bulgaria, Greece, and Romania – and Central Europe –
Hungary and Slovakia.[24]
Of note, only Denmark resisted German deportation efforts to the extent that
“everything went topsy-turvy.”[25]
Eichmann thought of the Denmark deportation as a failure.[26]
She devotes an additional chapter to describe the intensity of killing centers
in Eastern Europe, specifically Poland, the Baltic states and parts of Russia.[27]
Her point in spending so much time on these areas is that the trial itself
spent a great deal of time laying out the chronological background of the
Holocaust. Arendt considers this a trial problem because for purposes of
connecting criminal evidence to Eichmann, the background information “had no
apparent bearing upon the case.”[28]
She
wraps up the book briefly covering the insufficient evidence used to convict
him and the rapid manner in which Israel executed him after his conviction. Two
days after his conviction, Israel hung Adolf Eichmann, bringing dignity to
those who died under his hand. Ironically, Eichmann, went to his death, as
Arendt, put it “with great dignity” too.[29]
The closure she gave to Eichmann’s trial represented the closure the Jewish
people deserved. More abstractly, it represented the closure she felt Eichmann
deserved for having endured the test of what she felt was legal failure.
Arendt, did not, however, sympathize with Eichmann. Rather she sympathized with
what his trial should have stood for – justice.[30]
Arendt says:
the failure of the Jerusalem court consisted
in its not coming to grips with three fundamental issues, all of which have
been sufficiently well known and widely discussed since the establishment of
the Nuremberg Tribunal: the problem of impaired justice in the court of the
victors; a valid definition of the “crime against humanity”; and a clear
recognition of the new criminal who commits this crime.[31]
Altogether,
Arendt concludes that “the trial had been unfair, the judgment unjust.”[32]
Interestingly, Arendt did for Eichmann what the prosecution and defense failed
to do. That is, she laid out evidentiary evidence of Eichmann’s motives, and
lack thereof, and of his role, and again lack thereof, in both directly and
indirectly causing the deaths of millions of Jews (and others).[33]
In
laying out her argument in this fashion, Arendt juxtaposes Eichmann’s role as a
Nazi official with the procedure of the trial itself. The juxtaposition grows
with intensity as she approaches her closing argument. The effect demonstrates
that although Eichmann was full of flaws that led to unthinkable acts, the
trial too was full of procedural flaws. In Arendt’s view, they did less to
uphold the institution of law than to satisfy deeply held Jewish vengeance. She
notes that “Israel herself…confused the issues further by listing a great
number of purposes the trial was supposed to achieve, all of which were
ulterior purposes with respect to the law and to courtroom procedure.”[34]
Arendt carried this method of juxtaposition in more subtle ways through the use
of irony and sarcasm.
For
instance, one of the problems Arendt identified with the trial was with
Jerusalem’s claim to jurisdiction as opposed to Germany’s or an international
criminal court. She illustrates in the background chapters that Jews throughout
Europe became a stateless people.[35]
Their statelessness gave Germany and other countries license to deport Jews and
apply such measures as a “Final Solution” on account of their statelessness.
Arguably, their (Germany and other European countries’) reasoning was based on
the question: who would challenge them? They assumed a de facto jurisdiction to deal with so-called Jewish problems.
Arendt points out, ironically, that Eichmann too became stateless when he hid
in Argentina. She argues “it was Eichmann’s de facto statelessness…that enabled
the Jerusalem court to sit in judgment on him.”[36]
Although she argues the issue of jurisdiction was “a clear violation of
international law” (with regard specifically to his arrest), she recognizes the
benefit of Israel transforming Jewish statelessness to a legitimate Jewish
state.[37]
In
another twist of irony, Arendt juxtaposes the anonymity of so many Jewish
people whose stories, until the trial, were never known. She had problems with
the prosecution using irrelevant storytelling to paint a picture, not of
Eichmann, but of the entire situation. To Arendt, this posed a legal problem of
evidentiary credibility because the stories had little to no bearing
specifically on his guilt. They did, however, release from anonymity the untold
stories of Jews individually and of the Jewish people collectively. She even
hypothesizes that events may have turned out differently had those stories been
known sooner: “how utterly different everything would be today in this
courtroom, in Israel, in Germany, in all of Europe, and perhaps in all
countries of the world, if only more such stories could have been told.”[38]
Ironically, it was Eichmann who escaped into anonymity until his capture.
Although Arendt believes his capture was at some level illegal, she acknowledges
the necessity of Israel having done so. She also recognizes he was a criminal.[39]
Along
with irony, Arendt illustrates certain aspects of the trial’s absurdity by
being absurd through the use of sarcasm. The most obvious example occurs in the
opening pages of the book when Arendt describes the trial as figuratively and
literally a “show trial”.[40]
She uses one of the cast members, the prosecutor, to show that the stated
intentions of the trial do not correspond to the underlying intentions: “For
‘if we shall charge [Eichmann] also with crimes against non-Jews,…this is’ not
because he committed them, but, surprisingly, ‘because we make no ethnic
distinctions.’”[41]
Sarcastically she challenges “Was it not logical to bring before the court all
the facts of Jewish suffering (which, of course, were never in dispute) and
then look for evidence which in one way or another would connect Eichmann with
what had happened?”[42]
She clearly takes issue with the manner in which the prosecution will tie
Eichmann to all the Jewish suffering rather than present evidence of the
suffering he imposed. Nevertheless, Arendt believes the benefits of the
prosecution’s attempts to connect Eichmann to Jewish suffering were in part
valid because she proposes an alternate narrative that should have been read by
the judges: “just as you [Eichmann] supported and carried out a policy of not
wanting to share the earth with the Jewish people…we find that no one, that is,
no member of the human race, can be expected to want to share the earth with
you. This is the reason, and the only reason, you must hang.”[43]
Arendt’s
sarcasm reveals her underlying feelings regarding the scope the Holocaust. One
senses her deep loathing of Nazi officials and other complicit conspirators
such as Carl Goerdeler who proposed payment for Jewish losses.[44]
She retorted that mistreatment such as robbery and gassing were “such
technicalities.”[45]
One also senses that she felt Eichmann deserved to confront his own fears. For
instance she quips that “It was a great pity that Eichmann and Becher could not
have been confronted with each other, and this not merely for juridical
reasons.”[46]
She explained that Kurt Becher was “an old enemy of Eichmann” implying that a
confrontation between the two might actually provide some entertainment – to
see Eichmann’s uncomfortable disposition upon witnessing his rival. Yet, she
also defends Eichmann when she described the likelihood of his joining a
moderate wing of the S.S., one which was too sophisticated for someone like
Eichmann who spoke in plain language and “called a spade a spade.”[47]
These
tones of sarcasm and literary irony provide the foundation of Arendt’s legal
brief. They allow her to establish both her disapproval of the technical
process of the trial, intended to uphold the institution of law, and her
recognition that the Jewish people resolve their suffering by convicting a true
criminal.
Conclusion
The
title holds Arendt’s thesis, as Amos Elon, suggests – that evil, at some level,
exists in a banal form.[48]
The problem with trying to interpret her thesis by applying a common definition
of banal, is that Arendt does not actual mean that evil, of the Nazi sort, is
commonplace. Rather, she clarifies her intention suggesting instead that the
horrible characteristic of evil, as demonstrated by Eichmann, is in the
thoughtlessness with which he administered the Final Solution.[49]
Her point is that Eichmann and other Nazi party members were neither
predisposed to commit such atrocities nor were they altogether mentally
twisted. Their systematic and mechanistic approach to murder, to the extent of
considering it “liquidation,” removed a human element from the act of killing,
replacing it with legalistic procedure. This procedural aspect of the way
Eichmann went about his job, as if he took more satisfaction in the
accomplishment of process than in the outcome of those processes, defines
Eichmann’s evil as banal, and, therefore, beyond thoughtful horror. One could
interpret that Arendt’s view of the “banality of evil” exceeds what is normal
evil, which is to say something inhuman and far worse than evil itself.
Despite
her misgivings with the trial, one important reason why Arendt sees the trial
as beneficial is that it reinforced the humanity of someone like Eichmann whose
defense analogized him to a cog, part of a larger machine with little to no
control of the machine.[50]
She very clearly explains how the trial transformed Eichmann from a
thoughtless, inanimate figure unwitting of his crime to a man in need of
justice:
But insofar as it remains a crime – and that,
of course, is the premise for a trial – all the cogs in the machinery, no
matter how insignificant, are in court forthwith transformed back into
perpetrators, that is to say, into human beings.[51]
The irony of the Eichmann case is
that he convicted the Jewish people (and others) to death within the scope of a
legal framework, albeit a distorted legal framework, while arguably Israel
condemned Eichmann through an extra-legal framework. Eichmann followed the law literally
whereas Israel created law ideally.
One
of the challenges one might have with the Eichmann trial is in rectifying the
unthinkable horror of atrocity from a supernatural sense by reducing
accountability to technical, legal, and contractual language. On one hand rests
a notion of moral judgment in the abstract sense; on the other rest derivations
of moral judgment – ethics – through strictly rational articulation. The former
wrestles with the soul. The latter wrestles with the man. But at what point does
one cross the line of legal framework whereby man must rectify the soul with
reality? And, to what extent does that rectification signify justification?
That is the nexus of Arendt’s controversial portrayal of the unjust trial of an
unjust man.
References
Arendt, Hannah. Eichmann in Jerusalem A Report on
the Banality of Evil. New York, NY: Penguin Books, 2006, First published in
1963.
[1]
I make the distinction that it was Israel, the state, that brought Eichmann to
trial and convicted him rather than articulate it was the legal architecture of
Israel or of any one person who did it. Throughout Arendt’s book, she
implicitly suggests that the trial represented something larger than
restitution of acts by a single person.
[2]
Arendt, Note to the Reader. She introduces her book explaining how she derived
the book from the series of stories she wrote for The New Yorker. The book is an expansion of those articles. The
remainder of this essay will refer to Eichmann
in Jerusalem as “Arendt” and will attempt to reference specific book
locations. Broader generalities derived from the book without specific page
references will be clarified by additional footnote commentary.
[3]
Arendt, p. 4.
[4]
Arendt, p. 253.
[5]
Arendt, p. 287. She concurs with the judges conclusion that the verdict
validated Israel as not only a legitimate international state but specifically
“’the State of the Jews.’” (emphasis
added)
[6]
Arendt, p. 280.
[7]
Arendt, pp. 3-4.
[8]
Ibid.
[9]
Arendt, p. 20.
[10]
Arendt, chapter 1 is titled The House of Justice.
[11]
Arendt, p. 254. In her Epilogue she notes the legal principle of nullum crimen, nulla poena sine lege
indicating she believes that at some analytical level, the examination of
Eichmann’s crimes ex ante could
exonerate him, strictly legally, of having committed a crime per se.
[12]
Arendt, p. 21.
[13]
Arendt, p. 135.
[14]
Arendt, p. 6. Arendt uses sarcasm to illustrate absurdity. One such absurdity
was that Israel tried Eichmann on behalf of the international community, for
crimes against humanity. However, Arendt, implies that Israel’s main goal was
to try him for crimes against the Jewish people.
[15]
Arendt, p. 57.
[16]
Arendt, p. 54.
[17]
Arendt. p. 49. She demonstrates this point throughout the book, but one of the
more illustrative examples is when she says, “The longer one listened to him,
the more obvious it became that his inability to speak was closely connected
with an inability to think, namely, to think
from the standpoint of somebody else.” (emphasis included)
[18]
Arendt, pp. 142-143. Arendt compares Eichmann to Kurt Becher, who was vastly
more enterprenurial whereas Eichmann was
[19]
Arendt, p. 53.
[20]
Arendt, pp. 121-122.
[21]
Ibid.
[22]
Arendt, pp. 124-125.
[23]
Arendt, pp. 125-126.
[24]
Consequently these are the titles of three sequential chapters.
[25]
Arendt, p. 172.
[26]
Arendt, p. 174.
[27]
Arendt, p. 206.
[28]
Arendt, p. 207.
[29]
Arendt, p. 252.
[30]
Arendt, p. 265 she clearly recognizes “the facts of the case were beyond
dispute.” Also, p. 274 she summarizes the fundamental failure of the Jerusalem
court.
[31]
Arendt, p. 274.
[32]
Arendt, p. 249.
[33]
It is important to note that not only Jews were deported to concentration and
extermination camps. Other ethnic and social minorities including Gypsies and
Poles.
[34]
Arendt, p. 253.
[35]
Arendt, p. 115 & 138.
[36]
Arendt, p. 240.
[37]
Arendt, pp. 286-287. She agrees with the judges verdict the trial in effect
recognized Israel as a Jewish state.
[38]
Arendt, p. 231.
[39]
Arendt, p. 288. She specifically calls him “one of the greatest criminals of
that period.”
[40]
Arendt, pp. 4-5.
[41]
Arendt, p. 6.
[42]
Ibid.
[43]
Arendt, p. 279.
[44]
Arendt, p. 102.
[45]
Arendt, pp. 102-103.
[46]
Arendt, p. 141.
[47]
Arendt, p. 145.
[48]
Arendt, p. ix.
[49]
Arendt, pp. 287-288. She says that contrary to being stupid, that Eichmann was
instead thoughtless and that thoughtlessness is not the same as stupidity.
[50]
Arendt, p. 57. Arendt revisits the cog theory in her postscript, p. 289.
[51]
Arendt, p. 289.
Tensions are high among students as they prepare for the 10th Class10th Annual Examination. Our website has all of the TBSE Madhyamik question papers to help students relax. TBSE 10th Model Paper Students will benefit from important questions as they prepare for their exams. Are you looking for TBSE 10th Class Important Questions? We will provide you with a pdf of previous papers as well as complete information about it.
ReplyDeleteApna Khata also referred to as E-Dharti which is an official portal for land records in Rajasthan State. The Department of Land Resources Development under the Ministry of Rural development has brought website through the national digital India land records modernization program. apna khata rajasthan Citizens of Rajasthan state can fetch their details of land by using their USN, GRN, and other details online. In the present day, the Government has been putting efforts to reduce the manual work and through Rajasthan Apna Khata it has aimed to provide all details of land online.
ReplyDelete